Epistemic Humility
Perhaps the
costliest of all mistakes in thinking is to affirm a contradiction. Most people recognize this intuitively. What can a juror think when the person on the
witness stand says he saw the accused commit the crime and that he did not see the accused commit the crime? Common sense is flummoxed by such blatant
self-contradiction. So we almost never
hear it. Instead, the witness may say he
saw the accused commit the crime and later, under close questioning, admit that
he was in no position to see the crime.
The attorney examining the witness would then draw the contradiction to
the attention of the jurors, confident that they would disregard testimony that
contradicts itself.
Formal
logic demonstrates exactly how bad self-contradiction really is. Suppose someone affirms a contradiction; say,
for example, “Orange juice contains vitamin C and orange juice does not contain vitamin C.” We would symbolize this as follows.
1.
O + ~O
Proposition 1 is a
self-contradiction. It is necessarily
false. But what happens if someone
affirms it? How about this: “Phil is
President of the United States”? We
would symbolize this as P. Given the
self-contradiction in 1, it is easy to prove P:
1.
O + ~O /therefore
P
2.
O from
1, by “simplification” (a basic rule of logic: if p+q, then p)
3.
~O from
1, by simplification again
4.
O v P from
2, by “addition” (another basic rule: if p, then p or q)
5.
P from
4 and 3, by “disjunctive syllogism” (p or q, but not p, so q)
Given an explicit contradiction it
follows that I am President. Of course,
this isn’t the only bizarre conclusion that follows from a
self-contradiction. Given an explicit self-contradiction, any proposition whatever follows
with deductive necessity. People who
affirm self-contradictions imply the truth of every possible proposition.
Someone might say: “Okay, so
what? Common sense and logic both
condemn self-contradictions. Let’s all
avoid contradicting ourselves and move on to something more interesting.”
But there is a problem: all sane people believe at least one
implicit contradiction.
“Really? How so?” you might
ask. The reason is that our beliefs do
not obey the rules of logic. Remember
that some weeks ago in Story and Meaning I
published this little argument.
I. One of the
easiest and most obvious inference rules in logic is the rule of
conjunction. If A is true and B is true,
then A and B is true. We make students
create the truth table for this inference mostly so they can practice building
truth tables. No one doubts that propositions
are conjunctive.
1. A
2. B
/therefore A+B
3. A+B 1, 2, conjunction
II. It may seem
counterintuitive, but the rule of conjunction does not apply to beliefs. It is axiomatic that if a person believes
something, she believes that it is true.
At first guess, we might think that if two beliefs are held to be true,
the conjunction of those beliefs must also be believed. But this is not so.
III. The best
way to prove this is to assume the opposite and see what happens. We will assume that beliefs are
conjunctive. On this assumption, if a
person considers proposition D and finds that she believes it, and then
considers proposition E and finds that she believes it, then she should believe
a new proposition: D + E.
Let us
imagine that our subject considers all her beliefs sequentially. We will let B1 stand for her first
belief, B2 for her second, and so on. After considering B1 and B2,
she should find that she believes B1 + B2. Soon after, she should also discover that she
also believes B1 + B2 + B3.
Now, human
beings hold an indefinitely large number of beliefs, but the number of beliefs
a person holds may be finite. Let’s
assume that it is. (If people hold an
infinite number of beliefs, my overall argument still holds.) Given enough time, our subject should find
that she believes the following proposition, which we will call proposition
omega:
Bω
= {B1, B2, B3, B4, …Bω}
where Bω is the last of her beliefs.
It will
interest some people that Bω is one of the beliefs that our subject
believes; that is, the subject’s class of beliefs is self-referential. The argument does not depend on this fact.
The problem
is this. No reflective person believes Bω. To the contrary: it is safe to say that all
reflective people believe the opposite, i.e. they believe ~Bω. To see that this is so, consider the meaning
of ~ Bω in ordinary English: "It is not true that all of my
beliefs are true," which is the same as saying, “At least one of my
beliefs is false.”
IV. All of us know
that among our indefinitely large class of beliefs, there are almost certainly
some that are wrong. If it were possible
to consider individually each one of our beliefs (neuropsychologically
speaking, this may be impossible) we would find that we think each one is
true. After all, that’s what it means to
believe something; you think that it is true.
And yet, we do not believe that all our beliefs are true. We have very great confidence that at least
one of our beliefs is false. But if
conjunction rules over beliefs, we ought to believe Bω. The fact that we do not believe Bω
shows that conjunction does not rule over our beliefs.
The
fact that conjunction does not rule over our beliefs should cause us some
pause. Conjunction is a basic inference
rule in formal logic. Common sense
supports the conjunction rule as firmly as it condemns self-contradiction. (Imagine serving as a juror when the witness
testifies that “roses are red” is true, and “violets are blue” is true, but
“roses are red and violets are blue” is not true.)
Here’s the
problem. If our beliefs obeyed the rule
of conjunction we would all believe Bω. But we don’t.
We believe ~Bω. There is a contradiction implicit
between what we would believe if we believed in accord with logic (Bω) and what we actually
believe (~Bω). If we actually affirmed this contradiction,
we would thereby imply every proposition.
The contradiction is
only implicit. I can only consciously
think about a tiny fraction of my beliefs at any time. If the beliefs I am presently aware of seem
coherent and true, I am satisfied with them.
Let us call the conjunction of all my present beliefs proposition CB
(for conjuncted beliefs). I may well
think CB is true while still affirming ~Bω,
because I have indefinitely many other beliefs, and at least one of them is
false.
What should we
do? When someone points out to me that
two of my beliefs contradict each other (something I wrote a year ago
contradicts what I say today), I face the awful danger of affirming a contradiction. Common sense says I should reexamine my
contradictory beliefs and modify or abandon one of them. Much experience shows that we ought to be
fallibilists. Very often we find that our
belief about this or that turned out to be wrong.
The
upshot of this meditation is this. We
need to be appropriately humble about our epistemic efforts. Our beliefs do not in fact obey the rules of
logic. That doesn’t mean we can abandon
logic. But the logical implication of my
current beliefs may show that one or more of my beliefs stand in need of
improvement.
No comments:
Post a Comment