Some Thoughts about Work, Part 1
Our people must learn
to devote themselves to doing what is good,
in order that they
may provide for daily necessities
and not live
unproductive lives.
Titus 3:14
(New International
Version)
In
“Driverless Cars” I speculated that someday driving would be illegal. Maybe that won’t happen; after all, people like to drive. But even if human piloted cars remain legal,
this much is almost certain: computer-driven vehicles will prove safer, more efficient,
and cheaper to operate than human driven cars, trucks, and buses. Some people disagree; they say a driver has
to be able to respond to ever changing conditions on the road, and no computer
program will be able to replicate human intelligence. Further, even if a computer could be made
smart enough to replace a human driver, it would be prohibitively expensive.
I’m not
going to wade into philosophical debates about artificial intelligence. Whether or not computers can be built and
programmed to achieve “true intelligence,” my driverless cars prediction can be
treated as simply that, a prediction.
Just wait and see if I’m right: Sometime in the 21st century,
perhaps in my lifetime, computer-driven vehicles will surpass human piloted
vehicles in terms of safety, convenience, and cost.
Consider
one implication of my prediction, i.e., that in America in the 21st
century, perhaps in my lifetime, nearly all driver jobs will disappear. Taxi drivers, bus drivers, long-haul
truckers, bus drivers, airport shuttle operators, forklift drivers, delivery
truck drivers, and many heavy-machinery operators will disappear from the
workforce. I’m no expert, but I guess
that amounts to several million jobs, and at least some of them are prime
examples of a vanishing species, well-paying blue-collar jobs that require no
college education.
As I write this in 2015, many of
our politicians and policy leaders worry greatly about income inequality. Since World War Two, America has lost huge
numbers of blue-collar middle class jobs as manufacturers have moved their
operations from the United States to countries with lower labor costs. Is this a problem, even a crisis? If so, political leaders disagree
dramatically about what to do about it. If
I am right about driverless cars, the elimination of most driver jobs will only
exacerbate the debate.
The advent
of driverless cars is thus one more example of technology eliminating traditional
job categories. Economists often point
out that this has been going on ever since human beings started inventing
things. Perhaps we only became aware of
the disruptive force of innovation in the last few centuries, as the pace of
technological change has grown ever faster.
Many
economists are pretty sanguine about the phenomenon. They speak of “creative destruction.” Someone invented machines that can weave
cloth from thread, which threw the cottage weavers of England into
unemployment. The children of the
peasant weavers were forced to move into industrial cities where they had to
find jobs in factories, jobs that their foremothers could never have
imagined. No doubt, the economists say, many
people suffered in the transition.
Workers were abused, cheated, robbed of their traditional way of life,
and for a time many of them experienced material conditions (crowded tenements,
polluted water, urban crime, etc.) undoubtedly worse than their parents. But, the economists say, eventually the
overall greater productivity of new technology permitted a higher standard of
living for everybody. Our 21st
century political leaders have adopted this attitude. In the face of ever-changing technology, they
urge better education and re-education for the workforce. We can’t stop technological change, policy
leaders say; but we can shape society so that people suffer less from economic
disruption. Leaders on the left say
public policies can be found that will more quickly spread the benefits of
greater productivity to all people. The right
replies that redistribution schemes (through taxation and social welfare
policies) interfere with creative destruction; we should trust market forces to
spread wealth around.
I’m not going
to wade into that debate either, at least not now. Instead, I want to reflect on “creative
destruction,” the technological elimination of jobs, from a philosophical and
theological standpoint. I think there
are profound questions about work,
questions that may have revolutionary implications for human life and morality.
In his
letter to Titus, the apostle Paul said that Christians needed to provide for daily necessities and not live unproductive lives. In context, it seems that Paul wanted the new
Christians in Crete to win a good reputation for the Jesus movement. (In the 1st century all Christians
were new Christians.) The believers
should be law-abiding, self-disciplined, honest, kind, and hardworking. In every way they ought to live so as to make
outsiders think well of Christianity.
Now, there have
been and still are interpretive debates about Paul’s letter to Titus. For example, in the 19th century,
Christians disagreed whether Paul’s instructions in chapter 2—“teach slaves to
be subject to their masters in everything”—was an authoritative endorsement of
slavery. Again, I’m not going to discuss
such disputes. I’m not interpreting Paul
here; I want to use him as an example.
Paul’s words exemplify a very nearly universal belief about the morality
of work, a belief that I think must be critically examined. Here is the belief in a raw, unrefined form:
The “moral law of labor”: Every person ought to work.
Even a little reflection shows that
as stated the “law” overstates the case.
Some people—infants, infirm old people, people suffering from certain
diseases; in short, anyone who is unable to work—have no duty to work. Their “daily necessities” must be provided by
others; that is, by those who are able to work.
So we modify the raw form:
The “moral law of labor” (revised): Every
person who is able ought to work.
In his
letter to Titus, Paul takes this maxim, or something like it, for granted. He assumes that everybody knows that people
ought to work. He wants Christians to
win a good reputation for the movement by living up to a commonly accepted
moral platitude. The fact that it is a
moral platitude shows that some people disobey it; that Paul had to instruct
new Christians to obey it shows that some of them were tempted to disobey it.
I said above that Paul’s words express a very nearly universal belief about work. Not just in the first century, and not just in the West. I’m confident that the positive moral value of labor is a universal judgment found in every culture throughout human history.
I said above that Paul’s words express a very nearly universal belief about work. Not just in the first century, and not just in the West. I’m confident that the positive moral value of labor is a universal judgment found in every culture throughout human history.
At this point some readers want to
object: Give me a break! You are a
philosopher and “wannabe” novelist, not an expert in anthropology. How could you possibly know that every
culture endorses some version of the moral law of labor?
I will answer that question in part
2 of this essay. After that, I will move
on to a more important question: Is the moral law of labor actually true?
Copyright © 2015 by Philip D. Smith.
All rights reserved. International copyright secured.
Arrggh. You have retained from Castles the habit of weekly cliffhangers!
ReplyDeleteSo now we have to wait around for weekly updates in an extended philosophical argument. If this were an essay on the moral value of practicing delayed gratification, I could live with it more peaceably.
You know, don't you, this kind serialization is both frustrating and addictive? That I came here for a Thursday morsel because for three years you relentlessly conditioned me to do so? That now, with Castles done months ago, the endorfin centers in my brain still fire when I realize it is Thursday, which sends me sniffing forlornly around this site looking for something about Martin Cedarborne and his probably futile project to redeem Milo and bring peaceful liberal democracy to Two Moons.
Pathetically, it might work. You might habituate me to philosophy about work, so that even on this less earthy fare I might become addicted.
Arrggh. You have retained from Castles the habit of weekly cliffhangers!
ReplyDeleteSo now we have to wait around for weekly updates in an extended philosophical argument. If this were an essay on the moral value of practicing delayed gratification, I could live with it more peaceably.
You know, don't you, this kind serialization is both frustrating and addictive? That I came here for a Thursday morsel because for three years you relentlessly conditioned me to do so? That now, with Castles done months ago, the endorfin centers in my brain still fire when I realize it is Thursday, which sends me sniffing forlornly around this site looking for something about Martin Cedarborne and his probably futile project to redeem Milo and bring peaceful liberal democracy to Two Moons.
Pathetically, it might work. You might habituate me to philosophy about work, so that even on this less earthy fare I might become addicted.
I would apologize, except it's too gratifying to know you're reading.
Delete