How to Not Hope
Hope looks
forward to some good future. The excess
of hope is presumption; the deficit of hope is despair.
Aristotle taught that moral virtues
fall between two vices, a vice of deficit and a vice of excess. For example, the virtue of generosity is
somewhere between stinginess, an unwillingness or reluctance to give in
situations where giving is appropriate, and prodigality, unreasonably giving
too much. One can miss the virtue of
courage through cowardice, too little willingness to face danger in situations
where facing danger is appropriate, and through foolhardiness, an irrational
taking on of risk and danger. This idea
is often called the doctrine of the golden mean. Aristotle warned that virtue should not be
thought of as a numerical average, as if courage was exactly balanced between
cowardice and foolhardiness; he thought courage was more often closer to rashness
than to cowardice. It takes good
judgment to know how a virtue should be expressed in a particular situation.
It’s important
to notice the role of good judgment, or reason, in Aristotle’s doctrine. Actually, the word he uses is phronesis, usually translated “practical
wisdom.” Aristotle thought the
intellectual virtue, practical wisdom, had a role in guiding and nurturing
moral virtues, such as courage, moderation, or generosity. It is only by phronesis that one recognizes that this is a situation requiring courage or that this is a situation requiring generosity. And if it is a situation requiring
generosity, it is phronesis that
helps one judge how much and in what way one ought to give. Someone who woodenly follows rules for giving
(e.g. “Always give ten percent of your income to your local church”) may find
herself creating trouble whereas the giver with practical wisdom effectively
blesses those around her.
For Thomas
Aquinas, Aristotle was “the philosopher.”
On most topics, Aquinas adopted Aristotle’s teaching as far as he could;
up to the point where Aristotle contradicted the Bible or the creeds of the
church. For example, Aristotle wrote
that the world might be an eternal creation of the unmoved mover (God), or the
mover may have caused the world at some point in time. Aquinas could not simply approve this
conclusion, since scripture and creed say that God created the world at a
certain point. So Aquinas said that philosophically, Aristotle was right;
though reason demands the existence of God (unmoved mover), it does not say
whether God creates the world at a time or continually creates the world. It is only by revelation that Christians know what Aristotle did not know, that
God created the world at a time.
Aristotle
did not identify hope as a virtue.
Guided by the New Testament, Aquinas had to acknowledge hope not only as
a virtue, but also as a particularly important one. (1 Corinthians 13:13: “These three remain:
faith, hope and love, and the greatest of these is love.”) Aquinas called these virtues “theological”
virtues, in that they focused on God and were “infused” in the believer by
God. Since “the philosopher” did not
know the Christian gospel, he could not be faulted for not discussing the
theological virtues. Aristotle’s ethics
was not wrong, merely incomplete.
Nevertheless, Aquinas adopted
Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean, and he applied it even to hope. Christian hope—the theological virtue—has the
same structure as natural hopes. A
person can go wrong about hope in two ways, through despair and presumption.
Let’s imagine a case of hope as a
natural virtue. Suppose Nancy would like
to gain a promotion at work. Obviously,
the promotion is a future outcome that Nancy desires. It is not a mere fantasy; if it were, Nancy
might wish for a promotion, but she wouldn’t hope for it. Nancy’s case fits Aquinas’s description of
natural hope: a desire for a future good that is possible but not certain. (Aquinas says that even animals can display
natural hope; the hound chases the hare only when he thinks he may catch it and
gives up the chase when it is impossible.)
On Aquinas’s analysis, the fact that Nancy wants the promotion does not
guarantee that she hopes for it.
First: despair. Nancy may think that her supervisor unfairly
favors Edith, who also works in the department.
Perhaps Nancy is convinced that she lacks the necessary
qualifications. Maybe she thinks that
she never gets a break. And so on. Though I just said that Nancy “thinks” or “is
convinced” of certain things, the elements of despair do not have to be
consciously cognitive. Nancy may just see the world (or the office) as
disallowing her promotion. Her feelings of inadequacy may play a role.
Vice can be just as complicated as
virtue. In another post, I adopted
Adrienne Martin’s suggestion that hope is a syndrome. Despair may also be a syndrome.
Second: presumption. Perhaps Nancy believes the supervisor
despises Edith. Maybe Nancy has recently
attended a seminar on positive thinking and she willfully repeats her hourly
mantra: “I am qualified, I am ready, and I will succeed.” Or maybe Nancy’s Uncle Fred, a vice-president
in the company, has taken to visiting the department every afternoon and Nancy
sees his presence as her lucky charm.
Aquinas would say that in neither
case does Nancy truly hope for the promotion.
A person doesn’t hope if she can’t see herself getting the good thing
she desires. Nor is it hope if she
thinks the good outcome is a sure thing.
Aquinas would apply the same
analysis to theological hope. What is
the good outcome the Christian desires? Ultimately,
the Christian desires the “beatific vision.”
One way to express this is to say that the Christian desires to know God
as an intimate friend.
Even a little reflection marks this
good as a very high goal indeed. How can
a finite person, someone who lives a few decades on Earth, hope to be a friend,
a companion, of an infinite, transcendent God?
How can a sinner who acknowledges his moral faults—yet knows that his
self-knowledge is at best partial (he probably has forgotten most of his sins)—be
comfortable with a perfectly holy God?
The more one contemplates the ontological gap between an infinite
Creator and a finite creature, the more one can fall into despair.
But that isn’t the whole
story. To escape despair, the Christian
must remember grace. The incarnate God
has done all the heavy lifting; by his death and resurrection, Jesus brings us
into fellowship with God. Christians,
Aquinas says, must recognize despair as a temptation. It is a vice.
If we persist in it, it is a sin, and a particularly dangerous one. The person who despairs will not repent,
because he somehow believes that not even God’s grace can save him.
Sometimes Christians go to the
other extreme. Perhaps they reflect for
a time on God’s love and grace to sinners, and they conclude that the great
good of friendship with God is a “done deal.”
In fact, God is already their pal.
There really is nothing to hope for.
This is the vice of presumption, and it has its own dangers. In its worst case, presumption sees no need
for the atoning work of an incarnate God, since God’s love always conquers all.
Hope is a virtue. Like other virtues, it can be improved by
habituation—by practice. Part of
practice is to recognize and reject despair and presumption.
No comments:
Post a Comment