Some Thoughts about Work,
Part 2
A little sleep, a little slumber, a
little folding of the hands to rest—
and poverty will come on you like a
bandit
and scarcity like an armed man.
Proverbs 6:10-11 (repeated verbatim 24:33-34)
(New International Version)
I concluded part one of this essay
by claiming that there is a universal moral law, recognized in every culture:
The
“moral law of labor” (revised): Every person who is able ought to work.
Obviously,
I have not gone round the world to survey existing cultures, nor have I scoured
history and anthropology texts searching for counter-examples. If I haven’t done the empirical research, how
can I be so confident? By engaging in
what might be called “experimental philosophy”:
Try to imagine an historical culture that had no moral preference for
labor. Once you realize that it can’t be
imagined, you realize it can’t be real.
Experimental
philosophy is not new with me.
Philosophers have long used thought experiments. Here’s one from the philosopher James
Rachels: How do we know that every society on earth has a moral rule favoring truth
telling? Well, try to imagine a society
in which people could lie at any time, in which there was no belief that other
people should tell the truth. Sometimes
I ask students to imagine a society that had no preference for telling the
truth, and I ask, “What time is it?”
Someone invariably says, “Four-thirty” (or some other incorrect
time). I then chide the class for not
being creative. If there is no
preference for truth, someone could just as well say “Oranges” as give a time.
You
see the point? Our preference for truth
telling is so deep in us that we struggle to imagine a society where that
expectation is entirely absent.
Different cultures have different rules about exceptions, that is, times
when it is right to lie—perhaps it is right to lie to outsiders, to save a
life, to spare someone’s feelings, and so on.
But no culture says it is
right to lie willy-nilly, at any time to any person for any reason. If there were no expectation of truth telling, language would collapse. We would grunt at each other.
Enough about truth telling. Let’s return to the moral law of labor. Can we imagine a culture that denied it? I believe that today we can, and I will explain below.
But for most of human history it seemed obvious to everybody that people
needed to work. Therefore, every culture
has had a moral preference for labor over idleness.
Why?
Why have we always believed that people have to work? The saying I cited above (which occurs twice
in Proverbs, an indication of its importance in the minds of the ancient sages)
points the reason, an explanation obvious to everyone in the ancient world. If you
don’t work, scarcity will overtake you.
Remember Paul’s words to Titus,
which I cited in part one of this essay.
He wanted Christians to work in order to “provide for daily
necessities.” We all recognize that
people have needs. Human life is impossible if these needs are
not met. For all human history (until
very recently, as I will explain) it has seemed obvious that many human needs
can only be met through human labor. And
it has seemed obvious that we need to work hard;
in the story of the fall (Genesis 3) God tells Adam that he will wrest his
living from the ground by the sweat of his brow. We hear echoes of an agricultural society in
both Genesis and Proverbs, but the value of hard work was just as plain in
pre-agricultural hunting or gathering societies. Mercantile and industrial societies
experienced the same truth. Throughout
human history, for most people in most societies, the margin for error was
small. A bad hunt, a bad harvest, a bad
year with fishing nets, a plague of locusts, a plague of germs, an
earthquake—peasants (i.e. most people) always lived close to economic
catastrophe. People needed to work hard
to gain even a small edge against starvation.
I hope I have done enough to defend
my assertion that the moral law of labor has been widely accepted. Now I need to address certain
complications. Later, I will ask whether
it is true.
(1) Immediately someone will ask about the
difference between needs and wants. Much
of the work we do aims at getting things we want but don’t absolutely need. At various times individuals have recognized
this fact, and they have said, in effect: “Hey folks! We don’t need to work so hard. If we learn to be content with only the
things we truly need, we can live better lives.” Epicurus, St. Francis, the Buddha, and Jesus
are among the voices that call us away from the unending pursuit of more. If these voices are right, then the moral law
of labor—Every person who is able ought
to work—has to be balanced with other moral values. When I say that the moral law of labor is
recognized in every culture, I do not imply that it is the highest or sole
moral value.
(2) What about people who work, but not to
procure necessities? The vast majority
of human beings have been peasant laborers (herdsmen, hunters, farmers, etc.),
but the history books are full of rulers and conquerors, prophets and priests,
poets and philosophers, musicians and scientists. If there are some “jobs” that don’t aim at
producing the necessities of life, does that undermine my proposition that he
moral law of labor is universal? No, it
doesn’t. Rulers, artists, and scientists
all engage in work; to that extent they obey the law of labor. But it is true that they do not work to
procure necessities, an extremely important fact. Some
work aims at producing non-necessary goods.
Such non-necessary goods include things like statues built to honor
conquering kings, new religious rituals, and philosophy books and novels.
(3) What is the difference between needs and wants? If I admit that some
people work to produce daily necessities and other people work to produce
non-necessary goods, shouldn’t I give a perspicuous account of the
difference? No. As an example, consider transportation. Transportation of human beings and material
goods has always been a necessity of life.
Even in the most technologically primitive cultures people needed to go
to work (the field, the lake, the forest) and bring the products of their work
back home (the cave, the tent, the house).
Over time, human beings met the transportation need by walking; by using
beasts of burden; by building rafts, canoes, and ships; by driving trucks,
cars, and buses; by building railroads; and by many other methods. Pretty clearly, transportation of some kind
is necessary to human life. But every
time people invented a new means of transportation (e.g. sailing ships), they
incorporated that technology into their economy. New forms of labor appeared, such as sailor, and the overall productivity of
human labor increased. Over time the
higher level of productivity made it unthinkable to go back to an economy
limited to earlier kinds of transportation.
Therefore, a particular mode of transportation may be considered
non-necessary, in that human life went on just fine before it was invented, and
a necessity, in that later forms of life require the higher productivity made
possible by that form of transportation.
Unfortunately,
in beginning this essay, I did not understand how its tendrils would
lengthen. It may become the blogger’s
equivalent of the blackberry bush. I
will continue my examination of the morality of labor in part three, next week.