4. The Syndrome Account of
Hope
Hope is directed toward possible future goods, and “true” hope
is directed toward possible future genuine
goods (so that we may regard Hitler’s hope of conquering Poland as a vice
rather than a virtue). But what is hope?
In the last chapter, we saw that
C.R. Snyder’s hope theory defines hope in purely cognitive terms. Hope is
the sum of perceived capabilities to produce routes to desired goals, along
with the perceived motivation to use those routes. Snyder and his colleagues recognized that his
theory contrasts with earlier thinking by psychologists, who thought of hope
mainly in terms of positive feelings. On
Snyder’s view, right thinking (that is, hope) will lead to positive affect
(that is, “hopefulness” or feeling hopeful).
Accordingly, hope therapy focuses on cognitive changes.
Philosophers have generally defined
hope very differently. Their analysis
starts with Thomas Aquinas.
Aquinas,
as I explained in chapter 1, distinguished the passion of hope from the virtue
of hope. Passion and virtue both look to
the future, but passions aim at goods in this world while the virtue of hope
aims at a transcendent good, eternal friendship with God. Aquinas further distinguished between
concupiscent and irascible passions.
Hope, both as natural passion and theological virtue, is irascible. That is, hope moves us to overcome obstacles.
Later
philosophers often ignored the complexities in Aquinas’ account. Hope, whether passion or virtue, desires a future good, and that good is
seen as possible (neither certain nor
impossible). For these philosophers,
hope is a desire combined with the judgment that the thing desired is
possible. Notice that the judgment in
this definition is very different from the cognitive elements of Snyder’s
definition. The modern philosophers’
definition of hope includes a judgment about the probability of some desired
future good whereas the judgment in Snyder’s theory concerns a person’s ability
to think up pathways and her motivation to use those pathways.
As
Adrienne Martin points out, most modern philosophers, from the 16th
century forward, dispensed with the categories (“concupiscent” and “irascible”
passions) that Aquinas used.[1] For them, and probably for most contemporary
readers, a passion is just a motivating emotion. Many philosophers of the last four centuries
simply substitute “desire” for “passion,” which produces what Martin calls the
“orthodox”[2]
definition of hope: “to hope for an outcome is to desire it while believing it
is possible but not certain.”[3] There is ironic humor in Martin’s use of
“orthodox,” since modern philosophers would blanche at being described that
way.
Martin
objects to the orthodox doctrine, in that it is overly simplistic. First, it leads to an equally “orthodox”
modern conclusion about hope: We ought to regulate our hopes by their
probability. The more unlikely the good
we desire, the less rational it is to hope for it. I will discuss Martin’s objection to this
advice concerning the rationality of hope in my next chapter.
Martin’s
second objection, which will occupy the rest of this chapter, concerns the
notion of “desire.” The “orthodox
definition” oversimplifies hope, making “desire” cover too much ground. Borrowing a word from Margaret Walker, she
says hope is a “syndrome” that combines feelings,
thoughts, modes of perception, and motivations.[4]
Let’s
explore this “syndrome” idea with an example.
Imagine a man, call him Alfred, living in 1730. Alfred is sick with some condition that makes
it hard to breathe. His doctor tells him
he has “consumption,” the disease we call tuberculosis. Alfred’s doctor recommends treatment of one
sort or another.
Alfred
knows, as do most people in his age, that consumption is a dread disease. Most people who get it waste away and
die. But some victims do get
better. Medical advice doesn’t seem to
make much difference. (Tuberculosis
bacteria would not be identified for another 150 years. In fact, the “germ” theory, that many
diseases are caused by microorganisms, had not been invented in 1730.)
We
can imagine that many “consumptives” in Alfred’s day had no hope of cure. They firmly expected their disease to end
their lives. Imagine, though, that
Alfred hopes to recover from his consumption.
How might this hope be expressed?
Feelings.
Perhaps this is the most obvious expression of hope. Compared to other consumptives, Alfred is
more cheerful. His moods are
“brighter.” He smiles more. But it is hard to describe Alfred’s feelings
without also mentioning other aspects of his hope.
Thoughts.
Alfred’s hope is expressed sometimes in beliefs, such as: “Some consumptives do get well,” or “My doctor
may be wrong about my condition,” or “God may see fit to heal me.” Other times, Alfred’s thinking consists of imagination; he pictures to himself what
it would be like to breathe freely again, or he sees himself taking on
long-term projects, e.g. marrying and having a family.
Perceptions.
Alfred’s hope changes the way he experiences the world. He wakes up and breathing seems easier
today—“Perhaps my recovery has begun.”
On another occasion, he feels weak or out of breath, but he perceives
this as a temporary setback. It’s easy
to imagine a contrast case, a consumptive who lives out his final months or
years in despair; he interprets every new pain as a sign of approaching death.
Motivations.
Alfred’s hope spurs him to act on his doctor’s advice. That is, if he trusts the doctor’s expertise;
it’s possible that Alfred hopes for a cure, but not through medicine, in which
case his hope might spur him to use some nature cure recommended by the village
healer-woman. In hope, Alfred might make
plans for the farm he will buy after he marries.
Such
an example Martin’s objection to the “desire + probability judgment” definition
of hope is correct, at least in regard to “desire.” From here on, I will adopt the “syndrome”
definition of hope. Hope is a syndrome of feelings, thoughts, perceptions, and motivations
aimed at a future good.
Martin aims her criticism primarily
at modern philosophers’ overly simplistic definition of hope. It turns out that it also reveals a weakness
in Snyder’s hope theory. Hope theory
assumes that the cognitive elements of hope are the essential part, that
cognitive changes drive affective changes.
The syndrome definition of hope suggests this is too simple. Phenomenologically, hope is complicated. I will return to this idea in a later
chapter, when I discuss Michael Bishop’s theory of positive causal
networks. Before that, though, we need
to explore Adrienne Martin’s defense of the rationality of hope.
[1] Martin, Adrienne. How We
Hope (2014). 4-5.
[2] In this context, Martin’s “orthodox
definition” means something like “the definition of hope commonly accepted by
modern philosophers except for those who follow Thomas Aquinas.” One detects a bit of ironic humor in this
usage.
[3] Ibid. 5.
[4] Ibid. 5-6.
No comments:
Post a Comment