Wishing and Hoping
I met Mark
Bernier at a philosophy conference. Each
of us read a paper about hope, so we naturally struck up conversation, and we
agreed to trade copies of our most recent books. I sent Mark my book, Why Faith is a Virtue, and he gave me his, The Task of Hope in Kierkegaard.
Mark is a
Kierkegaard scholar; I am not. Parts of
his book are given to arguing for his interpretations of Kierkegaard against
other scholars. Kierkegaard wrote many
of his books under various pseudonyms, and in many cases the “authors” recount
arguments made by fictional characters; it is an open question whether and to
what degree the characters and pseudonyms speak for Kierkegaard himself. It may be that Kierkegaard intended that his
own views be hidden, that his real goal was to force readers to reflect for
themselves.
In any
case, I’m not expert enough to adjudicate questions regarding the best
interpretation of Kierkegaard. My real
interest in Mark’s book is not in technical scholarship but in the larger
matter: hope. Whether or not Mark’s
interpretation of Kierkegaard best represents Kierkegaard’s actual thinking,
does his reading of Kierkegaard offer insights into hope?
Consider
the difference between a wish and a hope.
Both of these are what Bernier calls “pro-attitudes.” That is, we desire the things we wish and
hope for. The difference between them is
that we hope for things we think may happen, while wishing is not bound by
possibility. We can wish that past
events had been different, but we cannot hope that past events were anything
other than what they were. Hope, as
philosophers have often observed, implicitly contains an epistemic judgment
that the thing hoped for is possible.
Now,
sometimes we hope for relatively unimportant things. “I hope the Mariners win today’s game.” “I hope we aren’t late for the wedding.” “I hope the stock market goes up.”
But some of
our hopes are far more important. They
become central themes to our lives; they give meaning to our lives. In Shawshank
Redemption, Andy Dufresne spends years planning and working to escape
prison. Kierkegaard asks readers to
imagine a peasant boy who hopes to woo and marry a princess; the boy builds his
whole life around this possibility.
Cortez burned his boats after arriving in Mexico; he hoped to conquer
the Aztec empire, and he had no back-up plan.
We may call such hopes existentially
crucial hopes. (That’s not a term
from Kierkegaard or Mark Bernier. I made
it up. But it seems appropriate.)
Existentially
crucial hopes are not necessary ethical hopes.
Andy Dufresne’s hope to escape unjust punishment seems right, but Cortez’s
hope to conquer the Aztecs was cruel and evil.
The embezzler’s hope that his crimes will gain him a life of ease and
luxury is obviously immoral.
Hopes can
be dashed. I hope the Mariners will win
tonight, and when they lose, I suffer.
Kierkegaard points out that this applies to existentially crucial hopes
just as much as trivial hopes. The
peasant boy who has centered his life on his plan to woo the princess may one
day realize that he will never succeed.
He is no longer a youth, the princess never noticed him; she has married
a foreign noble, and she lives far away.
His hope is no longer a hope.
But, Kierkegaard says, it may remain a wish. It is impossible that he will ever win the
princess’s love, but he wishes that things had turned out otherwise. In a sense, the peasant boy’s wish holds the
remnants of his hope, and in those remnants the pain of his loss stays with
him.
Kierkegaard
acknowledges that the boy may, as we say, “get over” his lost hope. He may adopt other life plans. It may be wise to do so, since by moving on
he may lessen the pain of loss. (I think
that when a hope is existentially crucial, giving it up may be a crisis, akin
to conversion. In 1945, some Nazis
committed suicide rather than live in a world without Hitler. Their hope for a pure Aryan empire was
gone.)
Practically
speaking, Kierkegaard says, it may be wise to surrender the wish. But he advises against it. The wish keeps the pain of lost hope
alive. If we use it rightly, the pain of
lost hope will do us good. Any hope that
can be lost, thus transformed into a mere wish that things had gone
differently, must be a hope directed at temporal things: escapes, marriages,
empires, wealth, etc. Therefore, a
crushed hope may remind one—will remind one, if used rightly—that there is
another kind of hope, a hope than cannot be crushed.
True hope,
which Kierkegaard calls “authentic hope,” is directed at “the eternal.” By “the eternal” Kierkegaard means the God of
Christianity, resurrection of the body, everlasting life, and enjoyment of God
forever. Mark Bernier, along with other
philosophers, suggests that even if one does not identify the eternal in
explicitly Christian terms, Kierkegaard’s advice may still be right.
It’s
interesting that Kierkegaard’s distinction between mundane hopes and authentic
hope has a medieval parallel. Thomas Aquinas
distinguished between what he called the “natural passion” of hope and the
“virtue” of hope. Natural hopes aim at
the goods of this world, while the virtue of hope, properly so called, aims at
God and is infused in us by God. As
surprising as it might seem to us, it is possible that Kierkegaard never read
Aquinas. They may have come to
remarkably similar notions of hope independently.
Kierkegaard’s
“authentic” hope and Aquinas’s “virtue” of hope direct us toward transcendent
goods. But this hope is hoped now. The good that we long for is future, but the
longing centers our lives in this world.
We build our lives around it, and it makes moral demands on us.
The virtue
of hope, “authentic” hope, cannot be an afterthought, a tag-on. It must be, in the term I invented, existentially crucial. Of course, this does not mean that many
people today (and in Kierkegaard’s 19th century Denmark) won’t treat
eternal hope as trivial. People live
their lives, ostensibly committed to Christian dogma, while actually aiming at
escapes, marriages, empires, and wealth. They hope for these things—and heaven too, as
an afterthought. We should count it a
blessing, Kierkegaard would say, that our mundane hopes are so often crushed
and made into wishes, because the pain of our wishes may push us toward real
hope.
No comments:
Post a Comment