The Philosopher Who Feared Hope
The first
course I took as a Ph.D. candidate at the University of Oregon, in the fall of
1987, was Ethical Theory. (Actually, I
wasn’t a Ph.D. candidate; I was a provisional admit. Essentially, UO said, “Come and take a class
and see how you do.” After I wrote a
paper, they admitted me to the program.)
William Davie, the professor, had us read Iris Murdoch’s The Sovereignty of Good. Through that book and others, Murdoch greatly
influenced my thinking during my time at Oregon. My dissertation, Learning to Love: Philosophy and Moral Progress, is heavily
indebted to Murdoch. In later years I
discovered Diogenes Allen, a longtime professor at Princeton Seminary, whose
book, The Path of Perfect Love, was
equally shaped by Murdoch’s ideas.
Allen, now deceased, and I are both Christians who learned much about
love from the same explicitly non-Christian philosopher.
Murdoch was
a 20th century Platonist who believed in the Good, but not in
God. She quite consciously borrowed or
adapted Christian ideas, giving them nontheistic treatments, as part of her
moral philosophy. For instance, Murdoch
thought modern psychology, with its notion of an unconscious mind, gives a
pretty good picture of original sin.
Human beings are often unaware of the drives and fears that condition
our behavior; our selfishness consists in the way we see and evaluate other
people and things by their roles in our lives.
It is natural for us to see other people as furniture in our
worlds. So we have to fight against our
natural tendencies. In the moral life,
Murdoch wrote, the enemy is the “fat, relentless ego.”
Moral
progress is rarely easy, Murdoch thought.
We struggle to see our neighbors accurately. Sometimes, as if by magic, a person might be
freed (for a time) from egocentricity.
Murdoch’s novels (she wrote many) often describe a character jarred
loose from the fat ego, perhaps by illness or injury, or by a sudden
recognition of having sinned, or by a realization of death’s approach. Murdoch does not hesitate to label such
unexpected interruptions in egocentricity as “grace,” though she did not
believe in any God who might be the source of such grace.
It’s really
quite remarkable. Murdoch obviously knew
Christian theology. Sin, grace, prayer,
spiritual exercises—she used them all.
And she endorsed familiar Christian virtues: love, humility,
graciousness, etc. She just didn’t
believe in God.
Over the
years, I’ve revisited Murdoch’s book many times. In recent weeks I’ve had opportunity to
re-read Murdoch yet again—along with Diogenes Allen—as part of a directed study
with a student. I’ve been struck by the
Christian virtue Murdoch did not
endorse.
Repeatedly,
in The Sovereignty of Good, Murdoch
warns against “consolation.” She takes
it as clearly true that people ought to live morally good lives. We ought to struggle against selfishness,
even if we have evolved in such a way that egocentricity is natural to us. We ought to strive to see other people justly
and lovingly, even if experiences of clear vision are hard to find and fly away
quickly. Murdoch thought the “Good” was
real and ought to be the end goal of moral pilgrimage, even if we only get
small glimpses of it. The moral life is hard. Therefore, Murdoch thought, we will be
tempted to believe in things that promise to make it easier. And religion is full of such
consolations. We are tempted to believe
in a personal God who graciously helps us overcome selfishness. We are especially tempted to believe that God
will reward us in the end. Thus we will
be tempted to believe in fictions.
We must try
to be good, to fight the relentless ego, without consolations. In the end, Murdoch thought, we die. Our lives are tiny flickers in an
unimaginably old, dark universe. We must
pursue the good, but without hope. We
must, Murdoch thought, be “good for nothing.” Without expectation of reward, without hope
for final triumph, Murdoch believed the almost impossible task of fighting
egocentricity was obviously right. And yet, morality is not democratic; some
people may not see the importance of trying to see the world as it is, and
there is nothing in philosophical argument that can force them to see it.
It seems
that Iris Murdoch feared hope.
Perhaps she thought that if she
admitted consolation into the moral life, it would undermine the project of seeing rightly. How can I rightly love the other—how can I
see the other justly and lovingly—if I think all the while that my love will
benefit me? The “just and loving gaze”
can be corrupted into merely another way of protecting and enlarging the ego.
I say “perhaps.” I am not certain why Murdoch feared
consolation so much. But it strikes me
as sad—and unnecessary. Honesty often
compels us to admit we do things with mixed motives. Any husband, upon very little reflection,
will realize that doing kind things for his wife will redound to his own
advantage. “If my wife is happy, I’ll be
happy.” So the consoling, egoistic
motive is there, if he wants to pay attention to it. But the other-focused motive is also there;
it is enough to see that the kind deed will bless his wife.
I hope for the resurrection of the
dead, for a new heaven and new earth, for eternal friendship with God. These hopes are tremendously consoling. That fact alone, that these hopes are
consoling, does not move me to abandon them.