2. Hopes
In
its basic structure hope is directed to possible
future genuine goods. This chapter
will explore that idea.
The
notion of telos—an end or goal—is
built into hope. Since people aim at many different goals,
there will be many kinds of “hope.” Some
hopes, like Gollum’s hope to recover the one ring of Sauron after Shelob kills
the hobbits, are immoral. Is it
surprising that “hope” can aim at a bad thing?
As
far as I know, philosophers have not addressed this question in regard to hope,
but they have wondered about a parallel question in regard to courage. Everyone recognizes that courage is an
important virtue. Life confronts all of
us, at some time or another, with danger; seeing the danger, we are tempted to
do what we should not do or leave undone things we ought to do. Courage is the virtue of correctly facing
danger so that we are not diverted from right behavior. So far, so good.
But
what should we say about the “courage” of a Nazi prison camp guard? (This is the usual example in the literature,
but we can easily think of others.
Consider the courage of a 21st century suicide bomber as she
takes her place among shoppers in a crowded market.) The prison camp guard faces dangers that
tempt him from doing his duties, as he understands them. He certainly seems to exhibit courage in the
performance of those duties. But his
courage serves the evil purposes of a prison camp; it seems that it would be
better, all things considered, if he exhibited cowardice. Perhaps more prisoners would survive if he
were a coward.
Philosophers
respond to this question in different ways.
Some insist that a virtue must be a good thing, so the prison camp
guard’s “courage” is actually only a simulacrum of courage. The virtues imply one another, these writers
say. The Nazi prison camp guard lacks
the virtue of justice (as witnessed by his willingness to serve a thoroughly
evil regime), with the result that his seeming courage is actually a vice. Other philosophers deny that the various
virtues imply one another. On their
view, it’s possible to possess and practice some virtue(s) without having some
other virtue. They say the prison camp
guard and the suicide bomber may be exemplars of courage even though their
lives, taken as a whole, are vicious.
In
one sense—a practical sense—we don’t need to settle this debate. Both sides would agree that the moral ideal
incorporates many virtues. No morally
serious person would aim to develop courage without justice. We can treat the debate as semantic. One side defines courage more narrowly than
the other. Once we are clear about how
this or that author uses “courage,” we can read him or her accurately.
Now,
Thomas Aquinas uses “hope” in a specific narrow sense. Hope (like faith and love) is a “theological”
virtue, he says. True hope aims at our
highest and best end, friendship with God = felicity in heaven. Hope shares the basic structure of the
natural passion of hope, in that it aims at a future possible good. But natural man knows nothing about his true
end, eternal friendship with God. Even
the greatest of pagan philosophers, Aristotle, who has much to teach us about
other virtues, such as courage and temperance, says nothing about the
theological virtues. To this day,
philosophers in the Thomist tradition, such as Josef Pieper, will use Aquinas’
language. Strictly speaking, they will
say, “hope” should be reserved for the theological virtue. But they will also say, with Charles Pinches,
that “hope grows from hope.” We can
learn about theological hope by examining natural hope.
The
very structure of hope is teleological.
The ends we hope for matter. Here
are four general categories.
(1)
Some hopes are immoral, as when “Don Juan” (there are many such characters on
my television) hopes to seduce his neighbor’s wife. Hitler hoped to establish a thousand year
Reich. The immoral nature of the goal
infects the hope.
(2)
Some hopes are morally permissible, but seemingly unimportant; for example, I
hope the Mariners will win the pennant next summer. My neighbor may hope her roses flourish. Someone might argue that the innocence of
such hopes makes them morally praiseworthy, and there is much to be said for
such a view. “Innocent” hopes may be
individually unimportant, but a life without any such hope would be dull
indeed. Of course, there is a danger
that someone might give so much attention to an innocent hope (watching scores
of baseball games each summer) that he neglects some moral duty, in which case
the innocent hope has ceased to be innocent.
(3)
Some hopes are morally praiseworthy, even though they seem to be detached from
friendship with God or the coming of God’s kingdom. Consider my friend Bernie, who is dying of
brain cancer. He hopes to provide, by
means of life insurance and investments, for his children. Surely this is a worthy hope. Bernie is also an atheist. He has no hope of friendship with God, nor
does he hope that God’s will be done on earth.
Bernie could hope for a more just society in the future, and in a
metaphorical sense he might be said to hope for the “Kingdom of God,” but only
in a metaphorical sense. There are many
others like Bernie, who hope for human flourishing without any reference to
friendship with God. Such morally
praiseworthy hopes are not theological hope, as Aquinas defines it. Yet they are important, and that is why we
find secular philosophers giving more and more attention to hope as a virtue.
(4) The
theological virtue of hope aims for eternal friendship with God, according to
Aquinas. It seems to me we must add as a
corollary: theological hope aims for the Kingdom of God. Jesus proclaimed the coming of the kingdom;
Christians may properly hope for it.
The
boundaries between these categories are not bright and clear. Consider aspects of the kingdom of God: for
peace among nations, justice for powerless people, or the conversion of
non-Christians to faith in Christ.
Suppose someone focuses her hope on peace in some particular place—e.g.
peace between rebels and government in Colombia. Does her hope fit in category 3 or category
4? It is a morally praiseworthy hope and
it does partake of one aspect of God’s Kingdom.
In this
book I will use “immoral hope” to describe things like Gollum’s hope or Don
Juan’s hope. I will use “hope” for all
morally licit hopes. I quite agree that
some hopes are more important or “higher” than others, and I will use various
locutions to indicate differences. But
since the basic structure of hope is the same, I will use “hope” generically.